Videolar

17 Aralık 2017 Pazar

The Embodied Cognition View

The Embodied Cognition View

Ulaş Başar Gezgin


The emergence of body in relation to cognition as an area of interest does not coincide with the emergence of cognitive sciences. It would not be false to claim that body was neglected in the early stages of the history of cognitive sciences (Hirose, 2002). This asynchrony has been due to the Cartesian legacy of dualism for cognitive sciences (Anderson, 2003; Garbarini, & Adenzato, 2004; Mingers, 2001; Seitz, 2000). In Piagetian thought, which can be considered to be one of the early precursors of cognitive sciences, sensorimotor stage which by and large involves the bodily movements has not been considered as unique; it was merely one of the stages that is primitive and prior to higher levels of cognition (i.e. concrete and abstract operational thought) (Seitz, 2000).

From a philosophical point of view, Mingers (2001) claimed that the history of cognitive sciences consisted of three stages:
The first stage of “pure” consciousness or thought exemplies the disembodied Cartesianism of Husserl. The second stage focuses attention on our practical, engaged activity in the world, drawing on the (early) work of Heidegger. The third stage, that is only just developing, recognizes the inherently embodied nature of cognition based in part on the phenomenology of Merleau-Ponty” (Mingers, 2001, p. 104).

In the first stage, the Cartesian doubt leads the individual thinker to take introspection and its station, ‘mind’ as the secure foundation of all cognitive activities. It was claimed that the senses could be fallible, but the inner thoughts could not. Therefore, the computational paradigm that is dominant in the first stage was based on four principles that resemble Cartesianism:
separation between mind and body, that thinking consists of manipulating abstract representations; that these manipulations can be expressed in a formal language; and that this is deterministic enough to be embodied in a machine” (Mingers, 2001, pp. 106-107).

Anderson (2003) which provides a field guide for studies on embodied cognition outlines the first stage in similar lines and adds that this Cartesianism and the consequent cognitivism appeared in the history of artificial intelligence as GOFAI (good old-fashioned artificial intelligence). GOFAI’s basic thrust was that human intelligence could be simulated by machines in terms of computer programs and mind could be studied and simulated independent of body and brain.

In the second stage initiated by Dreyfus (1972), the notions of self-consciousness and intentionality on the one hand, and the continuity of cognitive activities along with other spheres of human life on the other were emphasized. A long quotation from Mingers (2001) provides a comprehensive outline of the second stage:
The main outlines are first, that cognition and thought is not an isolated, separate mental function but our normal everyday activity – our “being-in-the-world”. It is embodied in the patterns of behavior which are triggered by our interactions and which have developed through our structural coupling (Maturana & Varela, 1987). “Thinking” is not detached reflection but part of our basic attitude to the world – one of continual purposeful action. Second, knowledge does not consist of representations, in individuals’ heads, of objective independent entities. Rather, we make distinctions through our language in the course of our interactions with others, continually structuring and restructuring the world as we co-ordinate our purposeful activities. Third, that which is said does not occur de novo, but is grounded in our past experiences and tradition – the history of our structural couplings.
Fourth, the most important dimension of our actions as humans is language but we must change our view of language away from seeing it as representational and denotative towards seeing it as (social) action through which we co-ordinate our activity. Languaging takes place in conversations which become the central unit of analysis. Such conversations are networks of distinctions, requests and commitments, valid in respect of their acceptance by others rather than their correspondence to an external reality. Finally, the view of “problems” which computers can help “solve” must change. Problems are not objective features of the world, but the result of breakdowns within our structural coupling to objects or to others. When our activities do not succeed or our co-ordinations fail, our routine operation is disrupted and a “problem” occurs. This is always against a particular background, for a particular individual or group and the nature of the problem only becomes defined through the attempts to repair it” (Mingers, 2001, pp. 110-111).

By 1990s, an embodied understanding of cognition has risen. The research on the topic is still rare. There is no consensus on the objections of the advocates of the embodied cognition view, but an important number of scholars endorse similar objections against the former approaches in cognitive sciences (Ziemke, 2002). In the general outline, the embodied cognition view poses that the body is not accidental for human cognition (Gezgin, 2005). Most of the cognitive capabilities such as grammar are rooted in the body in the interactive sense. For example, Johnson (1987) and Lakoff, & Johnson (1999) trace the origin of grammar in bodily metaphors and Lakoff, & Nuñez (1997) claim that body is central to mathematical understanding since the metaphors behind the mathematical systems are based on bodily existence.

Another point posed by the embodied cognition position was the continuity of human beings as a species with higher levels of the evolutionary ladder. Likewise, the embodied cognition view considers human beings not as static beings but dynamic beings evolving and developing on the phylogenetic as well as ontogenetic lines. Furthermore, the embodied cognition position gives special emphasis to the implicit aspects of human cognition and claims that former approaches in cognitive sciences conferred an undue emphasis on explicit representation (Anderson, 2003, p. 126).

The embodied cognition view has been considered to be the third revolution in the history of cognitive sciences after the cognitive revolution of 1960s against behaviorism and the connectionist revolution of 1980s against symbolic approaches. It caused a reconceptualization of the notion of representations since representations are the core of cognitive sciences that was heavily influenced by Cartesian disembodiment (Markman, & Dietrich, 2000). Cognitive sciences prototypically consider motor systems as peripheral since it is thought that cognitive system applies over the motor system. In other words, cognitive system activates (or passifies in that sense) motor system which is a biological slave. Internal models are formed merely by the exposure to external entities and events (Keijzer, 2002). Likewise, historically, cognitive science was based on the assumption that cognition can be studied without regard to somatosensory system (Markman, & Dietrich, 2000). Embodied cognition view has questioned this view of superiority of cognitive systems over motor systems prevalent in cognitive sciences (Keijzer, 2002).

One of the two approaches within embodied cognition research, though in its infancy yet, completely rejects the notion of representation while the second approach suggests a revision in the notion of representation by heterogenizing the notion, in other words, by defining different levels and types of representation (Markman, & Dietrich, 2000). The first view intends to replace the notion of representation in cognitive sciences with self-organizing systems in biology such as genes. The self-organizing systems do not form representations (Keijzer, 2002).

The implications of the embodied cognition view for artificial intelligence studies are consistent with NFAI (new fangled artificial intelligence): Robotics are emphasized in contrast to developing computer programs (Hallam, & Malcolm, 1994); the study of genetic algorithms and cellular automata has emerged, and finally genes and neurons as the new metaphors for understanding and modeling human beings have been employed.

Of course, the embodied cognition view is not immune to criticisms. The most powerful criticism involves the cognitive differences or similarities of physically disabled individuals. If cognition is embodied, the objection continues, in the sense of being grounded in the body, then certain cognitive difficulties and inabilities would be observed in physically disabled individuals. This objection has hitherto not tested empirically. It needs empirical studies to decide (Anderson, 2003, p. 114).



References


Anderson, M. L. (2003). Embodied cognition: a field guide. Artificial Intelligence, 149, 91-130.

Dreyfus, H. (1972). What computers can’t do: a critique of artificial reason. New York: Harper & Row.

Garbarini, & Adenzato, (2004). At the root of embodied cognition: cognitive science meets neurophysiology. Brain and Cognition, 56, 100-106.

Gezgin, U. B. (2005). Bilişsel bilimler ya da yanıtlı-yanıtsız sorular demeti: insan, bilgisayar ve zeki davranış. Bilim ve Gelecek, 15, 6-11.

Hallam, J. C. T., & Malcolm, C. A. (1994). Behavior: perception, action and intelligence – the view from situated robotics. Philosophical Transactions: Physical Sciences and Engineering, 349(1689), 29-42. 

Hirose, N. (2002). An ecological approach to embodiment and cognition. Cognitive Systems Research, 3, 289-299.

Johnson, M. (1987). The body in the mind. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

Keijzer, F. (2002). Representation in dynamical and embodied cognition. Cognitive Systems Research, 3, 275-288.

Lakoff, & Nuñez (1997). The metaphorical structure of mathematics: sketching out cognitive foundations for a mind-based mathematics. In L. D. English (Ed.). Mathematical reasoning: analogies, metaphors, and images (pp. 2-89). Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.

Lakoff, G., & Johnson, M. (1999). Philosophy in the flesh: the embodied mind and its challenge to Western thought. New York, NY: Basic Books.  

Markman, A. B., & Dietrich, E. (2000). Extending the classical view of representation. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 4(12), 470-475.

Maturana, H., & Varela, F. (1980). Autopoiesis and cognition: the realization of the living. Dordrecht: Reidel.

Mingers, J. (2001). Embodying information systems: the contribution of phenomenology. Information and Organization, 11, 103-128.

Seitz, J. A. (2000). The bodily basis of thought. New Ideas in Psychology, 18, 23-40.

Ziemke, T. (2002). Introduction to the special issue on situated and embodied cognition. Cognitive Systems Research, 3, 271-274. 



Source: Gezgin, U. B. (2017). Cognition and Art: Essays on Cognitive Science and Art Narratives.



COGNITION AND ART: ESSAYS ON COGNITIVE SCIENCE AND ART NARRATIVES

Prof.Dr. Ulaş Başar Gezgin

COGNITIVE SCIENCE
1. The Embodied Cognition View
2. On Flanagan’s Ideas On Dreams and Ahead: An Attempt To Locate Dreaming Phenomenon Under The Superclass Of Consciousness
3. “The Pragmatics of Cartoons: The Interaction of Bystander Humorosity vs. Agent-Patient Humorosity.”
4. Integrationist School or on ‘Rethinking Language’.
5. On Steven Pinker’s ‘Language Instinct’ or Some Remarks on Evolutionary Psycholinguistics
6. On the (Im)Possibility of Psychotherapist Computer Programs: An Investigation within the Realm of Epistemology
7. Thai Language: A Brief Typology.

ART NARRATIVES
8. Armenians As Ingroups in William Saroyan’s Stories from the Framework of the Theory of Social Representations: A Social Psychological Inquiry.
9. A Critique of The Stories By South East Asian Writing Awardees
10. Mulholland Drive: Another impasse for the American film industry.
11. On 'About Schmidt'
12. On Black spirituals.
13. The possibility of an African American poetry.

Bio

Hiç yorum yok:

Yorum Gönder